Summary: an exploration of the dual nature of humour: a) whether it can uphold the ethical principles of respect and mutual upliftment whilst serving as a tool for transformation or b) whether it is performed merely at the expense of others, thus making it cruel or even anti-human. My interactions with Copilot draw primarily on the works of Aristotle, François Rabelais, Thomas Hobbes, Henri Bergson, Sigmund Freud, Bertolt Brecht, Mikhaïl Bakhtine and Lydia Amir.


Questioning Copilot on humour, comedy, laughter and the human condition mostly from a philosophical perspective


When I was in my last year of middle school (approximately 15 years old), a teacher mentioned one disturbing aspect of laughter: namely, that it tends to come at the expense of another human being by putting them down. This former teacher of mine (most probably deceased by now) also briefly referred to how this characteristic was treated by Aristotle and some medieval scholars.

During my high school or university years, I came across references to the theories of Thomas Hobbes, Henri Bergson, Sigmund Freud and others, or I read extracts (or even complete works) by François Rabelais, Bertolt Brecht and Mikhaïl Bakhtine.

On Tuesday of this week, I learned that a colleague of mine is a comedian in her free time and I also found myself at the receiving end of a joke made by someone else. This information, coupled with my experience as the target of a joke (albeit a harmless one), brought back memories of that still unexplored topic: that humour is often performed at the expense of other human beings, potentially dehumanising those on the receiving end. Consequently, I decided to turn to Copilot to explore whether humour 
be it laughter, comedy or ridicule can be demeaning, uncharitable or lacking in compassion.

My interactions with Copilot have revealed that reconciling humour or laughter with an ethical framework based on respect and mutual upliftment is indeed problematic. However, they have also demonstrated to me that humour or ridicule can serve not only as a tool for social criticism, but also as a means of revealing alternative perspectives by challenging deeply entrenched or simply habitual ways of thinking or/and behaving  that is, through humour’s transformative potential. The main authors touched upon during these interactions include Aristotle, François Rabelais, Thomas Hobbes, Henri Bergson, Sigmund Freud, Bertolt Brecht, Mikhaïl Bakhtine and Lydia Amir.

Unfortunately, my interactions with Copilot have displayed a very strong bias towards the academic
work of Lydia Amir (whom I had never heard of until today even though she has published nearly as much as John Morreall on this subject). As a result, I have attempted to counterbalance this by also mentioning Bertolt Brecht’s Verfremdungseffekt as well as the contributions of Rabelais and Mikhaïl Bakhtine (with their focus on the carnivalesque, the grotesque and heteroglossia). It is interesting to note that such biases have managed to make their way into the academic scholarship provided by Copilot on humour and its inherent tendency to come at the expense of other humans. I would assume that they stem from the biases of the humans who programmed or tinkered with the algorithms and instructions used by Copilot to answer my questions.

My interactions with Copilot are listed chronologically.
Anything in green, bold and/or yellow indicates my emphasis.

Please note that I have not verified the accuracy of all the references generated by Copilot. Some are genuine (I was familiar with some of them years before this query), but AI-generated output can sometimes include inaccuracies or fabricated details referred to as ‘AI hallucination’. There is at least one such instance here: Copilot states that it is ‘revisiting John Morreall’s contributions’ (apparently, the most prolific English language author on this subject) when in fact it touches upon only one of his works and only quite briefly.



Have any Western thinkers addressed the idea that comedy is often done at the expense of someone else and is therefore not ‘compassionate’ or ‘charitable’?

Yes, several influential Western thinkers have indeed examined the idea that much of comedy derives its effect by putting someone down − a dynamic that raises serious questions about whether such humour can ever be truly compassionate or charitable.

For example, Thomas Hobbes famously argued in his work Leviathan (1651) that laughter arises from a sudden sense of superiority − a moment when we recognise our own advantages in contrast to another’s shortcomings or misfortunes. According to Hobbes, this ‘sudden glory’ we experience implies that humour often depends on exploiting the perceived inferiority of others. In this view, the pleasure of laughter is not rooted in empathy but in a stark evaluation of others as deficient − a process hardly what one would call charitable.

Similarly, Sigmund Freud explored the mechanics of humour in his work Jokes and Their Relation to the Unconscious (1905). Freud argued that jokes and comic expressions serve as a socially acceptable outlet for repressed aggressive impulses. In this framework, humour can be understood as a vehicle for the release of hostility − an aggression that, when aimed at the misfortunes or weaknesses of others, underscores a lack of compassionate engagement. Both Hobbes and Freud, therefore, provide a theoretical basis for understanding why some forms of comedy might inherently fall short of embodying charity or care.

Moreover, modern cultural critics have revisited these themes. For instance, W. H. Auden examined what he called the ‘comedy of human suffering’, highlighting how certain comedic forms trivialise human pain rather than inviting empathetic reflection. Auden’s commentary suggests that while humour can indeed be a powerful mode of social critique, when it consistently relies on targeting the vulnerabilities or misfortunes of individuals, it risks becoming uncharitable
even cruel in its ethical implications[1].

This long-standing discussion remains highly relevant today, particularly in debates over whether comedy should ‘punch up’ (targeting the powerful or absurd structures of society) rather than ‘punch down’ (attacking the already vulnerable). The tension between eliciting laughter through superiority and fostering genuine empathy continues to shape both critical theory and the practice of comedy in our contemporary cultural landscape.

Would you be interested in exploring further how these ideas have evolved in modern comedy theory or perhaps diving into some concrete examples from contemporary comedians?

[1]   https://bigthink.com/guest-thinkers/w-h-auden-and-the-comedy-of-human-suffering/
[2]   https://philosophymt.com/the-philosophy-of-laughter-and-humor-an-exploration-into-the-essence-of-joy/



What about earlier thinkers?

Certainly. Long before Hobbes and Freud, early Western thinkers were already wrestling with the ethical tensions in comedy specifically, with the notion that humour frequently relies on putting someone down.

Plato and early Greek thought 
In several of his dialogues, Plato expressed a deep scepticism toward forms of art that mimicked or ridiculed others. Although he didn’t frame his critique in terms of ‘compassion’ versus ‘charity’ per se, Plato warned that humour which
devalues its subjects could lead to a kind of moral laxity. For him, art and rhetoric that incited derision risked disrupting the moral and social harmony of the community implying that laughter elicited at another’s expense was a sign of imbalance rather than of genuine virtue.

Aristotle’s nuanced view 
Aristotle, while more systematic in his treatment of drama and imitation (especially in his analyses of tragedy in the Poetics), also touched on the comic by examining how it often exaggerates flaws. In his view, comedy typically depicts a deviation from the ideal or norm
be it through the portrayal of a character’s folly or a distortion of human nature. By laughing at these deviations, the audience may be seen as revelling in a form of superiority over the flawed subject. This observation subtly raises the issue that such humour, rather than being an expression of mutual joy or insight, rests on the diminished state of another.

Early Christian perspectives 
Furthermore, early Christian thinkers, such as Augustine of Hippo, though not primarily focused on developing a theory of humour,
critiqued any behaviour including certain types of laughter that demeaned others. Their ethical framework emphasised humility, charity and compassion as cardinal virtues. In this light, humour that relied on ridiculing or belittling others was seen not only as morally suspect but as a distraction from the call to love one’s neighbour as oneself.

These early reflections laid the groundwork for later, more systematic explorations of humour
including the ideas of superiority and the ambivalence between mirth and cruelty later articulated by Hobbes. They remind us that the tension between a compassionately shared laugh and a laugh at someone else’s expense is a perennial concern in Western thought.

Would you like to explore further how these classical perspectives influenced medieval or Renaissance debates on humour, or perhaps how they resonate with today’s discussions on ethical comedy? 

[1]   https://open.ocolearnok.org/whatsfunny/chapter/introduction-the-three-theories-and-beyond/
[2]  https://philosophymt.com/the-philosophy-of-laughter-and-humor-an-exploration-into-the-essence-of-joy/



Yes, I would like to see both developed -- this with reference to your conclusion, which was: ‘Would you like to explore further how these classical perspectives influenced medieval or Renaissance debates on humour, or perhaps how they resonate with today’s discussions on ethical comedy?’

Let’s trace the evolution of these ideas, starting with medieval debates on humour and then moving into the Renaissance and finally connecting these historical concerns to today’s discussions on ethical comedy.

---

Medieval debates on humour

Medieval thinkers inherited, critiqued and reinterpreted classical ideas about ridicule and laughter. In the medieval period, humour was often interwoven with moral and religious ethics. On one hand, festive and carnivalesque celebrations provided an outlet where traditional hierarchies could be momentarily inverted, allowing common people to laugh at authority figures. On the other hand, a strong ethical current shaped by Christian morality − insisted on humility, charity and the dignity of every person, which made humour at another’s expense ethically suspect.

Scholars in recent years have examined how medieval comedy was not just a means to entertain but also to serve as a corrective force − a way to spotlight excesses and social ills. Works like those discussed in Ethics: Comedy in the Middle Ages outline how medieval thinkers were aware of the tension between laughter as a liberating social force and laughter as a
potentially demeaning act. In this view, humour that demeaned or exploited the vulnerable ran counter to Christian ideals of compassion, while satire aimed at the abuses of power could be seen as morally justified. This duality reflected a broader societal debate about whether laughter should build community and encourage moral reflection or simply reinforce existing hierarchies by targeting the less powerful [1]. 

[1] Ethics: Comedy in the Middle Ages. in the multi-volume encyclopaedia A Cultural History of Comedy: The Middle Ages, 1000-1400. Eds. Martha Bayless and Jessica Milner-Davis. London, UK.: Bloomsbury Publishing (2020).
https://www.academia.edu/33731308

---

Renaissance
debates on humour

The Renaissance ushered in a rebirth of classical learning, and with it came renewed debates over the proper role of humour. Humanists rediscovered texts by Aristophanes, Plautus and Terence, which led to lively debates regarding the ethical dimensions of comic performance. Renaissance scholars were not merely passive inheritors of classical thought; they actively debated whether the classical forms of comedy − often rife with crude humour and the ridicule of lower-class characters − could be adapted to serve a society deeply influenced by Christian values and a burgeoning sense of human dignity.

Works such as
Encountering Plautus in the Renaissance: A Humanist Debate on Comedy  illustrate how critics weighed the merits and drawbacks of classical comedy. They argued that while Plautus’s works provided an imaginative space for social critique, they also risked endorsing a form of laughter that came at the expense of the dignity of some individuals[2]. Similarly, discussions compiled in studies like Humour and Satire in the Renaissance reveal that Renaissance thinkers were particularly sensitive to the idea of laughter as a dual-edged sword: it could serve as a cathartic release that strengthened the community by highlighting folly or it could devolve into a practice that unjustifiably mocked the weak[3]. In essence, the Renaissance debate wrestled with the challenge of whether humour − in all its irreverence − could ever be fully reconciled with an ethical framework based on respect and mutual upliftment.

---

Resonances in today’s discussions on ethical comedy

Modern debates on ethical comedy continue to echo these historical concerns. Today’s discourse is often framed in terms of whether humour ‘punches up’ (targeting those in power or critiquing social norms) or ‘punches down’ (exploiting or belittling the vulnerable). This conversation is strikingly similar to the medieval and Renaissance concerns: can humour be both a liberating, corrective force and a form of social critique without slipping into cruelty?

Much like their medieval counterparts, contemporary critics insist on the importance of context and intent. They argue that
jokes which serve as incisive commentaries on social injustice can be a force for goodprovided they do not simply dehumanise those who are already marginalised. Similarly, just as Renaissance thinkers worked to reconcile classical models of humour with emerging ethical standards, today’s comedians and critics are tasked with navigating the delicate balance between free expression and compassion. The debate is ever-evolving, as societal norms change and the consequences of humour are debated in new public arenas − from social media to stand-up stages − making this a perennial issue that remains as vibrant as ever.

---

The interplay between historical perspectives and modern ethical debates invites us to consider deeper questions: How do our cultural contexts shape our understanding of what is humorous and what is harmful? In what ways can comedy be both a mirror for societal critique and a medium that demands ethical responsibility? Exploring these questions further might involve examining specific contemporary case studies or diving into philosophical texts that analyse humour’s transformative potential. Would you like to delve into some concrete examples from modern comedy or perhaps explore another facet of this fascinating interplay between ethics and humour?



I would rather ask you to dive into philosophical texts that analyse humour’s transformative potential.

Let’s dive into a rich vein of philosophical inquiry that examines humour’s capacity to transform our understanding of ourselves and society. Two streams of work particularly stand out: one emerging from affect philosophy and incongruity theory, and another offering an epistemological account of humour as a privileged access to deeper truths.

Affect philosophy and the transformative potential of laughter

In recent years, scholars working within the framework of affect philosophy have taken a fresh look at the role of laughter. One influential text is Affect Philosophy Meets Incongruity: About Transformative Potentials in Comic Laughter. In this work, the author synthesises ideas from affect theory − which emphasises the non-discursive, embodied aspects of our emotional states − with classical incongruity-based models of humour. The argument here is that laughter is not merely a reaction to something ‘funny’ in a superficial sense but a potent affective experience that disrupts our habitual ways of seeing the world. By momentarily dislodging us from our fixed mental frameworks, laughter creates a space in which new perspectives can emerge. This transformative moment is seen as a kind of cognitive and emotional reset, where rigid social and personal boundaries might be renegotiated, ultimately offering a corrective force against entrenched patterns of thought and behaviour[1][2].

Humour’s epistemic and ethical dimensions

Complementing this affective approach, Jeremy Barris’s recent work, Humour’s Privileged Access to Truth, Meaning and Goodness, offers a compelling exploration of humour as an epistemic tool. Barris contends that the disruptive nature of humour provides us with a unique vantage point − one that can reveal hidden truths about our lives and social arrangements. According to this perspective, the incongruity inherent in humour breaks us out of our routine ways of interpreting the world, allowing deeper insights to surface. In this sense, the laughter induced by humour is both a signal and a mechanism for transformative change. It disrupts taken-for-granted assumptions and encourages us to consider alternative, sometimes radical, reinterpretations of reality. This way of looking at humour underscores not only its capacity for social critique but also its potential for facilitating personal and collective ethical reflection[3].

Broader implications and further readings

Both of these approaches suggest that humour is far more than a mere relief from tension or a vehicle for ridicule. Instead, when analysed philosophically, humour reveals itself as a complex, dynamic process of transformation. Whether through the embodied shifts described by affect theorists or the epistemic breakthroughs identified by scholars like Barris, humour challenges and reshapes our understanding of truth, ethics and social norms. These insights build on and extend classical ideas − think of Henri Bergson’s early contributions in Laughter, which, although primarily focused on the social corrective function of comedy, already hinted at humour’s deeper role in realigning our perceptions.

This rich interplay of ideas invites further exploration. For instance, you might consider how these theories interact with earlier philosophical treatments by Bergson, or even Kant’s reflections on the nature of the sublime and the absurd. How might these classical notions underpin our modern understanding of humour’s potential to transform cultural and political landscapes? Alternatively, we could examine concrete examples from contemporary social movements or art, where humour functions not only as critique but as a genuine catalyst for change.

What direction would you like to explore further: more detailed philosophical case studies, additional readings from classical thinkers that laid the groundwork for these ideas or perhaps an application of these theories to specific moments in modern culture?



[Suggestion] What are some recommended texts on humour in philosophy?

Below is a selection of recommended texts and resources that have shaped − and continue to shape − the philosophical exploration of humour:

---

1. Henri Bergson − Laughter (Le Rire)

Bergson’s Laughter (published in 1900) is widely recognised as a foundational text in the philosophy of humour. In it, Bergson examines the ‘mechanical’ nature of humour, arguing that laughter functions as a social corrective. By exposing deviations from established norms, laughter not only signals what is absurd in the behaviour of others but also reinforces collective expectations. Many readers praise Laughter for its clarity and incisiveness, making it a perennial recommendation in discussions on humour’s deeper cultural and philosophical dimensions[1].

---

2. Lydia Amir − Philosophy, Humour and the Human Condition: Taking Ridicule Seriously

This text offers a comprehensive framework that integrates historical insights with modern philosophical inquiry. Amir delves into how ridicule − a common element of many humorous expressions − reflects the human condition in all its complexity. By framing humans as inherently ‘laughable’ yet capable of transcending their own limitations (a notion she terms Homo risibilis), her work connects classical thought to contemporary debates on the ethics and transformative potential of humour. This book is especially valuable for readers interested in how comedy can both mirror and challenge societal norms[2].

---

3. Adrian Camilleri’s online exploration: How is That Funny?! A Look at the Philosophy of Humour

For those who prefer a more accessible entry point, Adrian Camilleri’s online article on the philosophy of humour provides a spirited and thoughtful overview. By revisiting ideas from ancient philosophers like Plato and Aristotle and linking them to modern interpretations, the article serves as a concise primer on why humour matters not only as a source of amusement but also as a profound epistemic and ethical tool. This text is ideal for readers beginning to explore how laughter interfaces with our understandings of truth, society and self[3].

---

4. Additional considerations and collected essays

Beyond these key works, philosophical inquiry into humour is also enriched by various essays and forum conversations. For example, discussions on platforms like Reddit frequently point to Pirandello’s lesser-known essay ‘On Humour’
, which distinguishes between the immediate, visceral reaction of comedy and the reflective, often tragic awareness of humour. These collected insights help contextualise humour within both classical traditions (from the likes of Socrates, Plato and Aristotle) and more modern existential investigations as seen in texts by Kierkegaard and others[1].

---

Further directions


Each of these texts contributes uniquely to our understanding of humour as a phenomenon that transcends mere laughter. They reveal humour’s dual role: as a mirror reflecting societal flaws and a transformative force that can encourage profound ethical and existential introspection. Whether you’re drawn to the pioneering analysis of Bergson or the contemporary synthesis offered by Amir, these works invite you to reconsider how humour operates as both critique and catalyst within the fabric of human life.

Would you like to delve deeper into how any one of these texts has influenced modern ethical debates on humour, or perhaps explore further recommended readings on this subject?



[Suggestion] Can you recommend more contemporary texts on humour?

Here are several contemporary texts and resources that approach humour from a philosophical − or at least interdisciplinary − perspective, offering fresh insights into how humour operates in our lives, minds and societies:

1. Inside Jokes: Using Humour to Reverse-Engineer the Mind 
   This 2011 work by Matthew Hurley, Daniel Dennett and Reginald Bartholomew is an excellent example of blending philosophy with cognitive science and evolutionary theory. The authors argue that humour, far from being a mere anecdotal diversion, is a mechanism by which our minds reveal their inner workings. By dissecting how humour emerges from our cognitive architecture, they demonstrate that laughter can serve as a kind of mental reset − a way of challenging established thought patterns and inviting us to reframe our perspectives. This interdisciplinary fusion not only deepens our theoretical understanding of humour but also its transformative potential.

2. Humour, Seriously: Why Humour Is a Secret Weapon in Business, Life and Love 
   Published recently in 2021 by Jennifer Aaker and Naomi Bagdonas, this book takes a more applied yet philosophically informed approach. Although its main focus is on the practical benefits of humour in personal development and professional settings, it also delves into why humour resonates on a human level. Drawing on contemporary research from psychology and neuroscience alongside case studies from various industries, the book underscores how humour can help us cope with challenges and foster creative thinking. Its accessible style makes it a good entry point for those interested in how humour’s transformative potential is harnessed in everyday life.

3. Laughter: A Scientific Investigation 
   Robert R. Provine’s work − published at the turn of the millennium − is another key resource that, while primarily scientific in its approach, raises profound philosophical questions about the nature of laughter. Provine explores how laughter is woven into our social fabric and what its unconscious triggers reveal about human behaviour. This book is incredibly useful for anyone interested in the ‘why’ behind humour, linking empirical findings with broader questions about meaning, ethics and social interaction.

4. Revisiting John Morreall’s contributions 
   Although Taking Laughter Seriously (1983) by John Morreall comes from a period slightly earlier than what some now consider ‘contemporary’, it remains a touchstone in the philosophy of humour. Morreall’s work challenges us to see humour not as a simple response to incongruity or superiority but as a nuanced experience that can offer insights into human nature and social dynamics. His ideas continue to influence current debates, making his texts an essential bridge between classical humour theory and modern interdisciplinary approaches.

---

Additional avenues
Beyond these books, contemporary academic thought on humour is thriving in peer-reviewed journals such as the International Journal of Humour Research. These articles often explore cutting-edge questions − like the interplay of humour with identity politics, digital culture, or neuroaesthetics − and can serve as excellent supplements to the books listed above.

Each of these texts highlights a different facet of humour: its roots in our cognitive processes, its practical benefits in the modern world and its capacity to unsettle and transform entrenched ways of thinking. They not only invite us to laugh but also to reflect critically on why we laugh, what that says about our values and how humour can be a tool for personal and societal change.

Would you be interested in a deeper dive into any one of these works or perhaps a curated list of recent academic articles that further explore these themes?



Yes, give me this list of recent academic articles mentioned in your conclusion.

Below is a curated list of recent academic articles that delve into the philosophical dimensions of humour. These works focus on humour as an ethical, cognitive and transformative phenomenon − exploring how laughter might not just be a response to the absurd, but also a cultivated tool for rethinking our relationship with ourselves, others and the world.

---

1. How Can Philosophy Improve Your Sense of Humour? 
- Author: Lydia Amir 
- Publication year: 2024 
- Journal/publisher: The Philosophy of Humour Yearbook (De Gruyter) 
- Summary: In this thought-provoking article, Amir argues that humour is far more than a spontaneous reaction − it is a learned discipline with transformative potential. She shows how cultivating a philosophical sense of humour can help individuals reframe personal attitudes and societal norms, thereby contributing to a richer, ethically informed approach to life[1].

---

2. Humour in Philosophy − Theory and Practice 
- Author: Lydia Amir 
- Publication year: 2012 
- Journal: Philosophical Practice 
- Summary: This article examines the role of humour within philosophical discourse. Amir critically reassesses philosophy’s traditional ambivalence toward the comic by suggesting that acknowledging and integrating humour can deepen philosophical inquiry and challenge established modes of thought
[1].

---

 3. Philosophy’s Attitude Towards the Comic: A Reevaluation 
- Author: Lydia Amir 
- Publication year: 2013 
- Journal: European Journal of Humour Research 
- Summary: Here, Amir revisits historical attitudes within philosophy toward laughter and the comic. By reevaluating these views, she paves the way for a more integrated understanding of humour − a perspective that sees comic elements as crucial for exploring human vulnerability, creativity and resilience
[1].

---

4. Homo Risibilis 
- Author: Lydia Amir 
- Publication year: 2014 
- Journal: Philosophical Practice 
- Summary: In her exploration of the notion of ‘
Homo risibilis’ (the laughable human), Amir argues that recognising our inherent tendency to laugh opens up new avenues for understanding the human condition. This article intertwines the idea of hilarity with philosophical inquiry about the good life, suggesting that humour holds transformative ethical significance[1].

---

5. Taking the History of Philosophy on Humour and Laughter Seriously 
- Author: Lydia Amir 
- Publication year: 2014 
- Journal: The Israeli Journal of Humour Research 
- Summary: Calling for a reevaluation of the historical neglect of humour, this paper argues that philosophy has too often sidelined laughter and the comic. Amir contends that a serious engagement with humour is essential for a complete understanding of philosophical history − and that doing so can illuminate the deeper interconnections between joy, critique and ethical transformation
[1].

---

 6. The Tragic Sense of the Good Life 
- Author: Lydia Amir 
- Publication year: 2015 
- Journal: (Appearing [sic] in scholarly outlets such as Philosophical Practice
- Summary: This article skilfully blends comedic and tragic elements, suggesting that humour plays a vital role in articulating a balanced perspective on life’s inherent paradoxes. By examining how laughter coexists with suffering, Amir explores how humour can reveal profound truths about what constitutes a life well lived
[1].

---

Additional avenues: journals and series

For further reading, consider exploring recent issues of:
- International Journal of Humour Research: An interdisciplinary forum where philosophical perspectives are frequently interwoven with cognitive, social and cultural analyses of humour.
- Philosophy of Humour − New Perspectives (Brill, 2023): This series brings fresh scholarly contributions that critically examine humour’s role in ethics and human understanding from multiple vantage points.

Each of these articles and resources contributes to a broader conversation about the ethical and epistemic power of humour. They invite us to see laughter not only as a personal response but as a phenomenon with the profound capacity to transform our social and intellectual landscapes.

Would you like to dive deeper into any specific debate emerging from these texts, or perhaps explore how these philosophical perspectives are being applied to contemporary social or cultural movements?



Lydia Amir seems to have published several papers on this subject. As such, can you tell me a little more about her?

Lydia Amir is a contemporary philosopher whose work has significantly shaped interdisciplinary discussions about humour, blending deep existential insights with a critical appreciation for the comic as a transformative tool. Her scholarship revolves around the idea that humour is not merely a spontaneous response to the absurd but a strategic, self-referential process that enables individuals to confront and reframe the inherent tragedy of the human condition.

Her influential book,
Philosophy, Humour and the Human Condition: Taking Ridicule Seriously  (2019), presents an original worldview − what she terms Homo risibilis. In this framework, Amir suggests that by recognising and embracing our own contradictions (seeing ourselves as simultaneously serious and ridiculous), we create a pathway to mitigate the pain of unfulfilled desire and the existential tension that defines our lives. Rather than dismissing humour as trivial, she argues that it offers a profound corrective mechanism − a way to pause, recalibrate and even transcend the limitations imposed by traditional rationality[1][2].

Amir’s work draws on a rich tapestry of Western philosophical traditions, integrating insights from classical thinkers with modern cultural and ethical critiques. She interrogates the dynamics of ridicule and self-deprecation, suggesting that humour − when self-aware and thoughtfully deployed − can serve as both a mirror reflecting our deepest human vulnerabilities and a tool for ethical transformation. Her writings advocate for a compassionate use of humour that not only acknowledges life’s inherent absurdities but also reclaims them to foster mutual understanding and social resilience.

Her academic contributions extend beyond a single publication; through a series of articles and critical essays, Amir has opened up new debates on how humour functions as a kind of knowledge − a way of perceiving truth that traditional logical frameworks often overlook. Scholars in fields ranging from aesthetics to cognitive science have found her work a valuable resource for exploring how laughter can challenge entrenched hierarchies and create spaces for rethinking our collective values.

Would you be interested in exploring how her concept of
Homo risibilis has influenced broader debates in contemporary philosophy or perhaps a closer look at specific articles where she develops these ideas further?



Yes, please tell me a little more about how Homo risibilis’ has influenced contemporary debates on this topic from a philosophical perspective.

Lydia Amir’s concept of Homo risibilis has become a touchstone in contemporary philosophical debates on humour by challenging traditional antagonisms between seriousness and the comic. In her ground-breaking work, Philosophy, Humour and the Human Condition: Taking Ridicule Seriously (2019), she argues that the human predicament − a tension between the insatiable nature of desire and our limited ability to satisfy it − can be radically transformed by embracing our own inherent absurdity. This shift from viewing laughter as a mere reaction to the ridiculousness of others toward a self-referential, liberatory act marks a significant departure from older models of humour that often rested on superiority or ridicule.

At the core of the Homo risibilis framework is the idea that
recognising our own contradictions (being simultaneously important and absurd) dissolves rigid boundaries between the self and the other. Instead of humour simply reinforcing social hierarchies by laughing at those deemed inferior, self-directed laughter becomes a tool for ethical self-understanding and mutual recognition. This perspective has influenced contemporary debates by suggesting that the humble acceptance of our ridiculous nature can foster both personal resilience and a more egalitarian social ethic. It presents humour as a means to bridge divides − an approach that has resonated with those advocating for more compassionate and inclusive forms of social interaction[1][2].

Moreover, this framework has spurred discussions in contemporary philosophy regarding the nature of rationality itself. Traditional rationality often excludes the messy, embodied experience of laughter, relegating it to the margins of philosophical inquiry.
By arguing that humour − far from being an irrational indulgence − can serve as an integrated model of rationality, Amir has opened pathways for analysing how emotional, bodily experiences contribute to ethical reasoning and social cohesion. Philosophers are now more inclined to view humour not only as a peripheral phenomenon but as central to understanding how humans navigate the paradoxes of life. This has led to deeper exploration into areas such as moral psychology, where the interplay between humour, empathy and the human condition is examined as a key component in resolving conflicts and fostering inter-subjectivity.

The influence of
Homo risibilis is visible in debates that question whether humour should punch up’ (challenge established powers) or ‘punch down’ (reinforce existing social hierarchies). Amir’s work provides a robust philosophical foundation for arguing that self-deprecating humour − always mindful of its own absurdity − can be a democratising force. This concept invites critics and practitioners alike to reconceptualise humour as a strategy for transforming social relations and rethinking ethical obligations, rather than merely a vehicle for entertainment or escapism.

Would you like to explore further how these debates intersect with contemporary ethical or political issues, or perhaps dive into how cognitive science is complementing these philosophical insights?



Yes, let me please know how cognitive science might be complementing these philosophical insights.

Cognitive science has significantly enriched the philosophical discussion of humour by offering empirical evidence for some of the theories long proposed by philosophers. One notable development is the idea of humour as cognitive play. Research in this area explores how processing humour often involves a rapid shift in perspective − a reorganisation or ‘play’ of mental frames when our initial interpretation of a situation gives way to an unexpected twist. This aligns with philosophical ideas like incongruity theory, where humour arises from the tension between what we expect and what actually occurs. Studies employing methods such as fMRI have shown that regions involved in cognitive flexibility and reward processing light up when individuals are exposed to humorous stimuli, suggesting that our brains are actively engaged in restructuring meaning as we laugh[1][2].

Additionally, cognitive science has contributed to refining debates around whether humour rests solely on a sense of superiority or if it can serve as a transformative mode of understanding. Experimental work indicates that when individuals experience humour, the affective and cognitive components interact to either bolster social cohesion or challenge stereotypical ways of thinking. For example, by revealing the contradictions inherent in our mental models, humour encourages us to question rigid categories and norms − a process that philosophers like Lydia Amir have argued is fundamental to developing a more compassionate and self-aware worldview, encapsulated in her notion of
Homo risibilis. This interplay of cognitive, emotional and social processing not only lends concrete support to the philosophical claim that humour can be transformative but also suggests mechanisms by which humour might catalyse ethical reflection and social change.

Moreover, cognitive scientists have examined how humour affects memory, learning and even creativity. The process of resolving an incongruity − noticing a gap in our understanding, processing that gap and finally achieving a resolution − mirrors the process of insight seen in problem-solving. Philosophically, this has been interpreted as a moment of revelation or transformation, where established beliefs are momentarily upended in favour of a broader perspective. Such empirical insights dovetail with the philosophical emphasis on laughter as more than just a response to the absurd; it becomes a tool for emotional catharsis and intellectual renewal.

These lines of inquiry demonstrate a compelling synergy between cognitive science and philosophy. While philosophers have long speculated about the transformative and emancipatory potential of humour, cognitive science provides the neural and behavioural evidence supporting these claims. Together, they present a richer, more nuanced picture of how humour not only entertains but also reshapes our understanding of ourselves and our social worlds.

Would you like to explore specific cognitive experiments that illustrate these principles in action, or perhaps discuss how these insights are being applied in contexts such as education or therapy?


Does this allusion to a moment of revelation or transformation in which established are temporarily suspended have anything to do with Bertolt Brecht’s Verfremdungseffekt?

Brecht’s Verfremdungseffekt, often translated as the ‘alienation
’ or ‘estrangement effect’, is precisely designed to interrupt the automatic absorption of the audience in the narrative, forcing them into a reflective, self-aware stance. In essence, both Brecht’s technique and the cognitive − philosophical interpretation of humour involve a temporary suspension of established perceptions.

When we talk about a moment of revelation or transformation in humour, we refer to the sudden cognitive shift that occurs when an unexpected twist or incongruity is resolved − a process that recalibrates our mental framework. Cognitive science has illuminated how this split-second reorientation, marked by neural activations in regions related to cognitive flexibility and reward processing, mirrors the experience where established assumptions are momentarily set aside. This moment not only provides a burst of amusement but also hints at deeper insights or alternative ways of understanding a situation.

Similarly, Brecht’s Verfremdungseffekt employs techniques like breaking the fourth wall, episodic narrative structures and overt reminders that the audience is watching a constructed performance. These methods interrupt the spectator’s immersive experience, compelling them to examine the socio-political underpinnings of what they see. The effect is to create a reflective space in which the familiar is rendered unfamiliar, enabling viewers to question and analyse rather than passively accept the narrative[1][2].

Though the contexts differ − Brecht’s approach is fundamentally political and aimed at fostering a critical, engaged citizenry, whereas the cognitive moment in humour is often an inadvertent yet enlightening by-product of the brain’s processing of incongruity − the underlying mechanisms share a common theme. Both depend on the suspension of habitual thought, opening a window for new perspectives, insights or critiques to emerge.

This convergence of ideas reveals an intriguing interdisciplinary dialogue: while philosophers and cognitive scientists describe humour as a brief yet transformative interruption of our conceptual routines, Brecht explicitly harnessed that very concept to challenge theatrical conventions and, by extension, social order. Would you like to explore further how these mechanisms have been empirically studied in cognitive experiments, or perhaps delve into how modern theatre still draws on these techniques to provoke critical thought?




What about the following study ‘Le rire au pied de la croix : de la Bible à Rabelais’?


Le rire au pied de la croix : de la Bible à Rabelais
’ is a fascinating study that examines how humour functions at the interstice of the sacred and the profane, tracing a lineage from Biblical texts to the irreverent satire of Rabelais. In this work, Michael Andrew Screech explores how humour was embedded in religious narratives − an aspect often overlooked. For example, he notes that while the Old Testament depicts feasting, laughter and communal joy, the New Testament even contains elements of irony and parody in the portrayal of Christ, which later provided fertile ground for the bawdy and subversive humour found in Rabelais’s writings.

Screech’s work demonstrates that even in periods marked by strict religious dogma, laughter found a way to emerge as a form of both consolation and critique. This perspective resonates with modern cognitive and philosophical theories that see humour as a mechanism for momentarily suspending established perceptions − a process not unlike what Brecht achieved with his Verfremdungseffekt. However, while Brecht’s estrangement effect was explicitly designed to jolt audiences into reflective awareness of socio-political realities, the humour analysed by Screech functions on a more cultural and historical plane by unearthing a latent irreverence even within sacred texts and practices.

In essence, Le rire au pied de la croix
reveals that laughter has been a transformative cultural force for centuries. It not only provided a means to process the tensions inherent in religious life but also offered an early challenge to rigid hierarchies and interpretations of the sacred. By showing that the very traditions held in reverence could also serve as sources of humour, the study enriches our understanding of how humour can destabilise established norms and create spaces for reinterpretation.

This text, therefore, complements contemporary philosophical discussions − like those surrounding
Homo risibilis and cognitive shifting in humour − by underscoring that the power of laughter to unsettle and transform is not a modern invention but a timeless human strategy. The interplay of sacred narrative and subversive humour in Screech’s study helps us appreciate how humour has historically operated as both a mirror and a catalyst for change.

Would you be interested in delving deeper into specific examples from Rabelais’s work as illuminated by Screech, or perhaps explore further how these historical insights are being applied in current debates on the ethics of humour?

: [Amazon.fr: Le rire au pied de la croix : De la Bible à Rabelais](https://www.amazon.fr/Rire-pied-croix-Bible-Rabelais/dp/2227317302)
: [Goodreads: Le Rire au pied de la croix : De la Bible à Rabelais](https://www.goodreads.com/book/show/78970543)
: [AbeBooks listing](https://www.abebooks.co.uk/book-search/title/rire-pied-croix-bible-rabelais/)



Rabelais somehow brings to my mind the work of Mikhaïl Bakhtine. Is this association on my part warranted?

Your association is certainly warranted. Mikhaïl Bakhtine is renowned for his in-depth exploration of François Rabelais’s work, most notably in his seminal book, Rabelais and His World. In this work, Bakhtine introduces and develops the idea of the ‘carnivalesque’ − a subversive mode of humour that upends established social hierarchies and norms.

Key points of Bakhtine’s analysis of Rabelais

1. Carnivalesque spirit: 
   Bakhtine argued that Rabelais’s work embodies a carnivalesque spirit, where traditional authority and rigid social structures are temporarily suspended. Through an irreverent celebration of the grotesque body and profane humour, Rabelais’s texts create a space where societal rules can be inverted and questioned. This resonates with the idea of a moment of cognitive and cultural transformation, where established assumptions are disrupted − a theme not unlike what we see in modern discussions of humour’s transformative potential.

2. Grotesque realism: 
   Another core element of Bakhtine’s thought is the notion of grotesque realism. In Rabelais’s portrayals of the body − often exaggerated, bodily and earthy − there is a deliberate challenge to the sanitised representations of the divine and the official. This form of humour not only entertains but also liberates the community by revealing the vitality and complexity of life beyond strict moral or cultural prescriptions.

3. Subversion through laughter: 
   Both Bakhtine and modern philosophers (such as those discussing the notion of
Homo risibilis) examine how humour acts as a liberatory force. By laughing at the absurdity of rigid structures, audiences are granted a kind of epistemic and emotional respite. Bakhtine’s work shows that Rabelais’s humour is a form of resistancea way to reclaim agency in the face of authoritarian power. This idea of subversion through laughter directly parallels contemporary themes in cognitive science and philosophy that explore humour’s role in suspending conventional thought, thereby opening the door to new perceptions.

4. Dialogism and heteroglossia: 
   Bakhtine’s broader theories on language
specifically dialogism and heteroglossia also influence his reading of Rabelais. He sees the interplay of multiple social voices and perspectives in Rabelais’s writing, which enriches the text with complex layers of meaning and subversive potential. This plurality is part of what makes the humour in Rabelais’s work so potent, as it constantly challenges monologic (or one-sided) interpretations of society.

Why your association matters

Your linking of Rabelais to Bakhtine is not only historically and academically justified but also philosophically significant. Both Rabelais’s texts and Bakhtine’s analysis highlight the power of humour to transform by interrupting the seamless acceptance of prevailing norms and inviting reflective distance. This connection deepens our understanding of humour as a dynamic force in culture and society, capable of catalysing change through its very structure.

In light of this, Bakhtine’s framework provides rich theoretical insights that continue to influence contemporary debates on humour. His ideas offer a bridge between historical literary analysis and modern cognitive explorations of humour’s transformative potential.

Would you like to explore how these Bakhtinian ideas have influenced modern theatrical practices or further examine their implications for contemporary debates on ethical and political humour?



Lausanne, the above was published on the thirteenth day of the fourth month of the year two thousand and twenty-five.